Usuario:Mpagano/Cálculo lambda
En ciencias de la computación, el cálculo lambda es un sistema formal diseñado para investigar la definición de función (matemáticas), la aplicación de funciones y la recursión. Fue introducido por Alonzo Church y Stephen Cole Kleene en la década de 1930; Church usó el cálculo lambda en 1936 para dar una respuesta negativa al Entscheidungsproblem. El cálculo lambda se puede usar para definir qué es una función computable. La pregunta de si dos expresiones del cálculo lambda son equivalentes no puede ser resuelta por un algoritmo general y este fue el primer problema para el cual la indecibilidad pudo ser probada (aun antes que para el problema de la parada. El cálculo lambda tuvo una gran influencia en los lenguajes de programación funcional, especialmente en Lisp.
Se puede decir que el cálculo lambda es el lenguaje de programación más pequeño. El cálculo lambda consiste de un sóla regla de transformación (sustitución de variables) y un sólo esquema de definición de funciones. El cálculo lambda es universal en el sentido de que cualquier función computable puede ser expresada y evaluada usando este formalismo. Por lo tanto, es equivalente al formalismo de las máquinas de Turing. Sin embargo, el cálculo lambda enfatiza el uso de reglas de transformación y no se preocupa de una máquina real que las implemente. Es una aproximación más relacionada con el software que con el hardware.
Este artículo trata sobre el "cálculo lambda sin tipos" como lo concibió originalmente Church. Desde entonces se han desarrollado algunos cálculos lambdas tipados.
Historia
[editar]Originally, Church had tried to construct a complete formal system for the foundations of mathematics; when the system turned out to be susceptible to the analog of Russell's paradox, he separated out the lambda calculus and used it to study computability, culminating in his negative answer to the Entscheidungsproblem.
Informal description
[editar]In lambda calculus, every expression stands for a function with a single argument; the argument of the function is in turn a function with a single argument, and the value of the function is another function with a single argument. A function is anonymously defined by a lambda expression which expresses the function's action on its argument. For instance, the "add-two" function f such that f(x) = x + 2 would be expressed in lambda calculus as λ x. x + 2 (or equivalently as λ y. y + 2; the name of the formal argument is immaterial) and the number f(3) would be written as (λ x. x + 2) 3. Function application is left associative: f x y = (f x) y. Consider the function which takes a function as argument and applies it to the argument 3: λ f. f 3. This latter function could be applied to our earlier "add-two" function as follows: (λ f. f 3) (λ x. x+2). The three expressions
- (λ f. f 3) (λ x. x + 2) and (λ x. x + 2) 3 and 3 + 2
are equivalent. A function of two variables is expressed in lambda calculus as a function of one argument which returns a function of one argument (see currying). For instance, the function f(x, y) = x - y would be written as λ x. λ y. x - y. A common convention is to abbreviate curried functions as, for instance, λ x y. x - y.
The three expressions
- (λ x y. x - y) 7 2 and (λ y. 7 - y) 2 and 7 - 2
are equivalent. It is this equivalence of lambda expressions which in general can not be decided by an algorithm.
Not every lambda expression can be reduced to a definite value like the ones above; consider for instance
- (λ x. x x) (λ x. x x)
or
- (λ x. x x x) (λ x. x x x)
and try to visualize what happens as you start to apply the first function to its argument. (λ x. x x) is also known as the ω combinator; ((λ x. x x) (λ x. x x)) is known as Ω, ((λ x. x x x) (λ x. x x x)) as Ω2, etc.
While the lambda calculus itself does not contain symbols for integers or addition, these can be defined as abbreviations within the calculus and arithmetic can be expressed as we will see below.
Lambda calculus expressions may contain free variables, i.e. variables not bound by any λ. For example, the variable y is free in the expression (λ x. y) , representing a function which always produces the result y . Occasionally, this necessitates the renaming of formal arguments, for instance in order to reduce
- (λ x y. y x) (λ x. y) to λ z. z (λ x. y)
If one only formalizes the notion of function application and does not allow lambda expressions, one obtains combinatory logic.
Definición formal
[editar]Formalmente se comienza con un conjunto numerable de identificadores, sea {a, b, c, ..., x, y, z, x1, x2, ...}. El conjunto de todas las expresiones lambda se puede describir por la siguiente gramática libre de contexto en BNF:
Las primeras dos reglas generan funciones, mientras que la tercera describe la aplicación de una función a un argumento. Normalmente los paréntesis para las abstracciones (regla 2) y para la aplicación de funciones (regla 3) se omiten si no hay ambigüedad, con la convención de que (1) la aplicación asocia a izquierda y (2) liga toda la expresión que sigue. Por ejemplo, la expresión puede ser escrita como .
Lambda expressions such as λ x. (x y) do not define functions because the occurrence of the variable y is free, i.e., it is not bound by any λ in the expression. The binding of occurrences of variables is (with induction upon the structure of the lambda expression) defined by the following rules:
- In an expression of the form V, where V is a variable, this V is the single free occurrence.
- In an expression of the form λ V. E, the free occurrences are the free occurrences in E except those of V. In this case the occurrences of V in E are said to be bound by the λ before V.
- In an expression of the form (E E′), the free occurrences are the free occurrences in E and E′.
Over the set of lambda expressions an equivalence relation (here denoted as ==) is defined that captures the intuition that two expressions denote the same function. This equivalence relation is defined by the α-conversion rule and the β-reduction rule. Sometimes an alternate equivalence relation, obtained by adopting a third rule called η-conversion, is used.
α-conversion
[editar]The alpha-conversion rule is intended to express the idea that the names of the bound variables are unimportant; for example that λx.x and λy.y are the same function. However, the rule is not as simple as it first appears. There are a number of restrictions on when one bound variable may be replaced with another.
The alpha-conversion rule states that if V and W are variables, E is a lambda expression, and
E[V := W]
means the expression E with every free occurrence of V in E replaced with W, then
- λ V. E == λ W. E[V := W]
if W does not appear freely in E and W is not bound by a λ in E whenever it replaces a V. This rule tells us for example that λ x. (λ x. x) x is the same as λ y. (λ x. x) y.
β-reduction
[editar]The beta-reduction rule expresses the idea of function application. It states that
- ((λ V. E) E′) == E[V := E′]
if all free occurrences in E′ remain free in E[V := E′].
The relation == is then defined as the smallest equivalence relation that satisfies these two rules.
A more operational definition of the equivalence relation can be given by applying the rules only from left to right. A lambda expression which does not allow any beta reduction, i.e., has no subexpression of the form ((λ V. E) E′), is called a normal form. Not every lambda expression is equivalent to a normal form, but if it is, then the normal form is unique up to naming of the formal arguments. Furthermore, there is an algorithm for computing normal forms: keep replacing the first (left-most) formal argument with its corresponding concrete argument, until no further reduction is possible. This algorithm halts iff the lambda expression has a normal form. The Church-Rosser theorem then states that two expressions result in the same normal form up to renaming of the formal arguments iff they are equivalent.
η-conversion
[editar]There is a third rule, eta-conversion, which may be added to these two to form a new equivalence relation. Eta-conversion expresses the idea of extensionality, which in this context is that two functions are the same iff they give the same result for all arguments. Eta-conversion converts between λ x. f x and f whenever x does not appear free in f. This can be seen to be equivalent to extensionality as follows:
If f and g are extensionally equivalent, i.e. if f a==g a for all lambda expressions a, then in particular by taking a to be a variable x not appearing free in f nor g we have f x == g x and hence λ x. f x == λ x. g x, and so by eta-conversion f == g. So if we take eta-conversion to be valid, we find extensionality is valid.
Conversely if extensionality is taken to be valid, then since by beta-reduction for all y we have (λ x. f x) y == f y, we have λ x. f x == f; i.e., eta-conversion is found to be valid.
Arithmetic in lambda calculus
[editar]There are several possible ways to define the natural numbers in lambda calculus, but by far the most common are the Church numerals, which can be defined as follows:
- 0 := λ f x. x
- 1 := λ f x. f x
- 2 := λ f x. f (f x)
- 3 := λ f x. f (f (f x))
and so on. Intuitively, the number n in lambda calculus is a function that takes a function f as argument and returns the n-th composition of f. That is to say, a Church numeral is a higher-order function -- it takes a single-argument function f, and returns another single-argument function.
(Note that in Church's original lambda calculus, the formal parameter of a lambda expression was required to occur at least once in the function body, which made the above definition of 0 impossible.) Given this definition of the Church numerals, we can define a successor function, which takes a number n and returns n + 1:
- SUCC := λ n f x. f(n f x)
Addition is defined as follows:
- PLUS := λ m n f x. m f (n f x)
PLUS can be thought of as a function taking two natural numbers as arguments and returning a natural number; it is fun to verify that
- PLUS 2 3 and 5
are equivalent lambda expressions. Multiplication can then be defined as
- MULT := λ m n. m (PLUS n) 0,
the idea being that multiplying m and n is the same as m times adding n to zero. Alternatively
- MULT = λ m n f. m (n f)
The predecessor PRED n = n - 1 of a positive integer n is more difficult:
- PRED := λ n f x. n (λ g h. h (g f)) (λ u. x) (λ u. u)
or alternatively
- PRED = λ n. n (λ g k. (g 1) (λ u. PLUS (g k) 1) k) (λ v. 0) 0
Note the trick (g 1) (λ u. PLUS (g k) 1) k which evaluates to k if g(1) is zero and to g(k) + 1 otherwise.
Logic and predicates
[editar]By convention, the following two definitions (known as Church booleans) are used for the boolean values TRUE and FALSE:
- TRUE := λ x y. x
- FALSE := λ x y. y
- (Note that FALSE is equivalent to the Church numeral zero defined above)
Then, with these two λ-terms, we can define some logic operators:
- AND := λ p q. p q FALSE
- OR := λ p q. p TRUE q
- NOT := λ p. p FALSE TRUE
- IFTHENELSE := λ p x y. p x y
We are now able to compute some logic functions, as for example:
- AND TRUE FALSE
- ≡ (λ p q. p q FALSE) TRUE FALSE →β TRUE FALSE FALSE
- ≡ (λ x y. x) FALSE FALSE →β FALSE
and we see that AND TRUE FALSE is equivalent to FALSE.
A predicate is a function which returns a boolean value. The most fundamental predicate is ISZERO which returns TRUE if its argument is the Church numeral 0, and FALSE if its argument is any other Church numeral:
- ISZERO := λ n. n (λ x. FALSE) TRUE
The availability of predicates and the above definition of TRUE and FALSE make it convenient to write "if-then-else" statements in lambda calculus.
Recursion
[editar]Recursion is the definition of a function using the function itself; on the face of it, lambda calculus does not allow this. However, this impression is misleading. Consider for instance the factorial function f(n) recursively defined by
- f(n) = 1, if n = 0; and n·f(n-1), if n>0.
In lambda calculus, one cannot define a function which includes itself. To get around this, one may start by defining a function, here called g, which takes a function f as an argument and returns another function that takes n as an argument:
- g := λ f n. (1, if n = 0; and n·f(n-1), if n>0).
The function that g returns either the constant 1, or n times the application of the function f to n-1. Using the ISZERO predicate, and boolean and algebraic definitions described above, the function g can be defined in lambda calculus.
However, g by itself is still not recursive; in order to use g to create the recursive factorial function, the function passed to g as f must have specific properties. Namely, the function passed as f must expand to the function g called with one argument -- and that argument must be the function that was passed as f again!
In other words, f must expand to g(f). This call to g will then expand to the above factorial function and calculate down to another level of recursion. In that expansion the function f will appear again, and will again expand to g(f) and continue the recursion. This kind of function, where f = g(f), is called a fixed-point of g, and it turns out that it can be implemented in the lambda calculus using what is known as the paradoxical operator or fixed-point operator and is represented as Y -- the Y combinator:
- Y = λ g. (λ x. g (x x)) (λ x. g (x x))
In the lambda calculus, Y g is a fixed-point of g, as it expands to g (Y g). Now, to complete our recursive call to the factorial function, we would simply call g (Y g) n, where n is the number we are calculating the factorial of.
Given n = 5, for example, this expands to:
- (λ n.(1, if n = 0; and n·((Y g)(n-1)), if n>0)) 5
- 1, if 5 = 0; and 5·(g(Y g)(5-1)), if 5>0
- 5·(g(Y g) 4)
- 5·(λ n. (1, if n = 0; and n·((Y g)(n-1)), if n>0) 4)
- 5·(1, if 4 = 0; and 4·(g(Y g)(4-1)), if 4>0)
- 5·(4·(g(Y g) 3))
- 5·(4·(λ n. (1, if n = 0; and n·((Y g)(n-1)), if n>0) 3))
- 5·(4·(1, if 3 = 0; and 3·(g(Y g)(3-1)), if 3>0))
- 5·(4·(3·(g(Y g) 2)))
- ...
And so on, evaluating the structure of the algorithm recursively. Every recursively defined function can be seen as a fixed point of some other suitable function, and therefore, using Y, every recursively defined function can be expressed as a lambda expression. In particular, we can now cleanly define the subtraction, multiplication and comparison predicate of natural numbers recursively.
Computable functions and lambda calculus
[editar]A function F: N → N of natural numbers is a computable function if and only if there exists a lambda expression f such that for every pair of x, y in N, F(x) = y if and only if f x == y, where x and y are the Church numerals corresponding to x and y, respectively. This is one of the many ways to define computability; see the Church-Turing thesis for a discussion of other approaches and their equivalence.
Undecidability of equivalence
[editar]There is no algorithm which takes as input two lambda expressions and outputs TRUE or FALSE depending on whether or not the two expressions are equivalent. This was historically the first problem for which the unsolvability could be proven. Of course, in order to do so, the notion of algorithm has to be cleanly defined; Church used a definition via recursive functions, which is now known to be equivalent to all other reasonable definitions of the notion.
Church's proof first reduces the problem to determining whether a given lambda expression has a normal form. A normal form is an equivalent expression which cannot be reduced any further. Then he assumes that this predicate is computable, and can hence be expressed in lambda calculus. Building on earlier work by Kleene and constructing a Gödel numbering for lambda expressions, he constructs a lambda expression e which closely follows the proof of Gödel's first incompleteness theorem. If e is applied to its own Gödel number, a contradiction results.
Lambda calculus and programming languages
[editar]Most programming languages are equivalent to the lambda calculus extended with some additional programming language constructs. The classical work where this viewpoint was put forward was Peter Landin's "A Correspondence between ALGOL 60 and Church's Lambda-notation", published in CACM in 1965. The key point is that the lambda calculus expresses the kind of procedural abstraction and application useful for any programming language. Prominently, functional programming languages are basically the lambda calculus with some constants and datatypes added. Lisp uses a variant of lambda notation for defining functions, but only its purely functional subset is really equivalent to lambda calculus.
Actually implementing the lambda calculus on a computer involves treating "functions" as first-class objects, which turns out to be rather difficult to accomplish using stack-based computer languages. This is known as the Funarg problem.
Theory of the lambda calculus says that lambda calculus computations can always be carried out sequentially, not that they must be carried out sequentially. The lambda calculus is suitable for expressing some kinds of parallelism — for example, call by future evaluation. However, the lambda calculus does not in general implement concurrency; related calculi (such as the π calculus) have been designed to overcome this limitation.
See also
[editar]- SKI combinator calculus
- H.P. Barendregt's Lambda cube
- Jean-Yves Girard's System F
- Thierry Coquand's calculus of constructions
- Typed lambda calculus
- Curry-Howard isomorphism
- Anonymous recursion
- Unlambda
- Knights of the Lambda Calculus
References
[editar]- Abelson, Harold & Gerald Jay Sussman. Structure and Interpretation of Computer Programs. The MIT Press. ISBN 0262510871.
- Barendregt, Henk, The lambda calculus, its syntax and semantics, North-Holland (1984), is the comprehensive reference on the (untyped) lambda calculus; see also the paper Introduction to Lambda Calculus.
- Church, Alonzo, An unsolvable problem of elementary number theory, American Journal of Mathematics, 58 (1936), pp. 345–363. This paper contains the proof that the equivalence of lambda expressions is in general not decidable.
- Punit,Gupta, Amit & Ashutosh Agte, Untyped lambda-calculus, alpha-, beta- and eta- reductions and recursion
- Henz, Martin, The Lambda Calculus. Formally correct development of the Lambda calculus.
- Kleene, Stephen, A theory of positive integers in formal logic, American Journal of Mathematics, 57 (1935), pp. 153–173 and 219–244. Contains the lambda calculus definitions of several familiar functions.
- Larson, Jim, An Introduction to Lambda Calculus and Scheme. A gentle introduction for programmers.
Some parts of this article are based on material from FOLDOC, used with permission.
External links
[editar]- L. Allison, Some executable λ-calculus examples
- Georg P. Loczewski, The Lambda Calculus and A++
- David C. Keenan, To Dissect a Mockingbird: A Graphical Notation for the Lambda Calculus with Animated Reduction
- [[Category:Mathematical logic
- [[Category:Computational models
- [[Category:Logic in computer science
- [[Category:Lambda calculus
- [[Category:Theoretical computer science
- [[Category:Formal methods